Chance and Purpose in Evolution
An
Examination of Evolutionary Biology and its Teleological Implications
The relationship between science and
religion has been characterised by the diverse range of interactions between
the two disciplines. The conflict thesis advanced in the nineteenth century by
John William Draper and Andrew Dickson White, which sees science and religion
as being in a state of constant warfare, has been thoroughly repudiated in
recent years and replaced by a model that acknowledges the complexity of the
issues involved.[1] One such
issue concerns the relationship between Darwinian evolution and Christian
theology. Initially, this relationship would appear to be characterised by
conflict; for, on the one hand, it is central to a Christian worldview that
humans are understood to be the purposeful creation of an all-powerful creator.
They bear the image of God, having been chosen “in Christ before the foundation
of the world…”[2] On the
other hand, a scientific worldview maintains that humans are the product of
evolution, a seemingly directionless process that is governed by chance and
contingency. The chance-like nature of evolution seems to undermine the notion
that humans are the deliberate creative act of a purposeful God. However, this
essay will argue that this conclusion is not necessarily warranted. The
question will be posed: Do the contingent
and chance-like processes inherent in Darwinian evolution undermine the belief
that human beings have been purposefully created? In order to answer this
question, this essay will be examining the extent to which teleological
conclusions, particularly those that refer to purpose and chance in evolution,
can legitimately be inferred from biological observations. Firstly, the history
of the relationship between teleology and biology will be explored so as to
provide a context within which to situate the current debate. Secondly, the
teleological implications of Darwinian evolution will be examined. This essay
will argue that evolutionary biology supports a theologically neutral,
teleological approach to the development of life. It will also argue that a
theistic understanding of teleology is not undermined by evolutionary biology.
Examining Teleology
Before continuing, it is important to
establish what is meant by the term “teleology”, for it is susceptible to
misinterpretation and oversimplification. Essentially, teleology is a mode of
explanation that seeks to understand a phenomenon with reference to its
specific telos, a Greek word denoting
a ‘goal’ or an ‘end’.[3]
In this essay, the term teleology will be understood to indicate the
recognition of a phenomenon that is purposeful or directional. As an approach
to the natural world, teleological thinking has played a prominent role in the
sciences. Although, during the scientific revolution, a significant shift
occurred away from thinking about the telos
of an object or phenomenon, teleological thinking remained prominent in the
biological sciences.[4]
It wasn’t until around 1970 that the rejection of teleology in evolutionary
biology came to be regarded as axiomatic truth.[5] For Paul F. Lurquin and Linda Stone, any
notion of teleology lies outside the realm of scientific inquiry. They write
that “teleology, the notion that natural events occur for a predetermined
reason imagined by a designer, is unscientific and unprovable.”[6]
David Hanke agrees, but goes further still, asserting that any talk of
teleology or purpose “is entirely subjective because purpose has no real
existence outside the mind of the animal thinking of it.”[7]
Both of these approaches reject the notion that teleology has any place in
evolutionary biology. However, these assertions rest upon two presuppositions
which, if found to be false, will call the elimination of teleology into
question. The first is that teleology cannot avoid a theistic interpretation,
necessarily having religious implications. The second presupposition is that
teleology is unobservable, that it is an a
priori assumption that has been imposed upon the scientific process, which cannot be inferred from biological
observation.
It is understandable that teleology
would be conflated with theism. This is largely because various teleological
arguments, such as the design argument, have come to be associated with the
strident claims made by the advocates of creationism and intelligent design.[8]
Nevertheless, there is good reason to suppose that teleology is open to both
non-theistic and theistic interpretations. Alister McGrath writes that
teleology “can be a neutral term, more phenomenological than theoretical,
designating simply the observation that certain behaviours or functions appear
to be goal-directed; it can also be used in a more developed sense,
articulating the idea of processes being directed or driven toward a goal by
internal or external forces or agencies.”[9]
Indeed, when one considers the initial development of teleological thinking, it
becomes apparent that teleology lends itself to neither theistic nor
non-theistic approaches. Although the term was introduced in the eighteenth
century, the idea of teleology goes back to the classical period and the works
of Plato and Aristotle.[10]
Aristotle and Plato argued that a process can only be properly understood if
its end, or telos, takes explanatory
priority. For Plato, the appearance of design that is exhibited in the universe
should be attributed to the purposeful work of a powerful being, or demiurge,
that stood outside the creative process. Although often considered to be a
being of great power and knowledge, this demiurge did not create the universe
but moulded it. However, as Robert J. Richards has noted, the demiurge “may
simply have been Plato’s stand-in for the rational structuring of the universe. [11]
Aristotle, on the other hand, avoided talking about external causes; instead he
attributed the teleological drive within nature to a network of internal causes.
Referring to the building of a house, he argued that each step of the process
can only be fully appreciated if the overall layout of the structure is
understood. He then extended this approach to the natural world, arguing that
the generation of living organisms, and their parts, can also only be fully
appreciated if the end or goal of the process is understood.[12]
Aristotle’s approach clearly permits a theological interpretation of teleology,
which Thomas Aquinas developed in the Middle Ages.[13]
Nevertheless, Aristotle avoided interpreting teleology in theistic terms such as
the design of an external creator. Instead, he understood teleology to denote internalised
purposes.[14] It is
imperative, therefore, to distinguish between design and teleology. McGrath
emphasises this when he writes, “design is to be understood as conscious intent
and artifice applied externally to the order of nature, in order to achieve
some end or external goal; teleology can be interpreted simply as evidence of
function or purpose within nature, as an expression of natural laws and natural
order.”[15]
During the seventeenth century, the
Aristotelian approach to natural philosophy gave way to a more mechanistic view
of the universe.[16]
Although teleology did not remain unchanged, it continued to be a significant
consideration in this new mechanistic approach. Two quite dissimilar
understandings of teleology were developed in very different contexts. In
England, natural theology promoted a theistic understanding of teleology; while
in Germany, a neutral understanding of teleology was advanced. Natural theology
gained widespread acceptance in England, and continued to gain popularity into the
early nineteenth century with the works of William Paley.[17]
This system of thinking sought to prove God’s providential nature by appealing
to the apparent design displayed in the natural world. Because of this, design
arguments became an essential part of English scientific culture.[18]
However, while English natural theology understood teleology to be primarily
concerned with fulfilling the plans an external creator imposed upon the
universe, the approach taken in Germany was quite different.[19]
Immanuel Kant was critical of English natural theology. Essentially, he argued
that natural theology assumed the existence of God and his moral wisdom, while
trying to argue for these characteristics.[20]
For him, “there was no proof for the existence of God.”[21]
In contrast to the approach of English natural theology, Kant argued that
teleology was best understood as a method of interpreting how the structure of
an organism relates to its processes. Rather than invoking a creator or a
design, Kant sought to understand specific phenomena by referring to the goal
or end that is achieved through them. In some cases this could be production,
such as the production of a house; whereas in other cases this could be
reproduction, such as in an organism. With this in mind, McGrath asserts that
“biological explanation thus has an ineradicably teleological dimension, even
though Kant interprets this in terms of the goals of the production,
reproduction, or maintenance of the biological organism, rather than the
imposition of the ‘will’ of an external agent, such as God.”[22]
Teleology in Biology
At the turn of the nineteenth century, the French scientist Georges Cuvier developed an approach to biology that emphasised the role of teleology in the lives of specific organisms. Although, towards the beginning of the century, theories of evolution were becoming increasingly popular in scientific circles, Cuvier was not an evolutionist. Indeed, he advanced a teleological approach to biology
that would later come into conflict with evolutionary biology. Cuvier argued
that living organisms were not simply thrown together in a random fashion, but
that the individual parts of each organism were coordinated so as to promote
the well-being of the whole.[23]
This principle came to be referred to as the ‘Conditions of Existence’. Cuvier
wrote of these conditions that “as nothing may exist which does not include the
conditions which made its existence possible, the different parts of each
creature must be coordinated in such a way as to make possible the whole
organism …”[24] It was
his belief that these ‘Conditions of Existence’ operated according to general
laws which meant that specific parts of an organism would operate as if there
were specific goals for their activity. For example, the skeletal structure of
a vertebrate would be teleologically incompatible with the respiratory system
of an arthropod, because an insect would require a rigid external surface for
gas exchange through spiracles. Such a surface would make an internal skeleton
redundant.[25] The
point that Cuvier was making was that the potential of each individual part of
an organism could only be understood in reference to the organism as a whole.[26]
A significant consequence of this view,
however, is that it would come into conflict with the increasingly popular
evolutionary approach to biology. Cuvier had argued that the individual parts
of an organism were correlated in a tightly organised manner. These parts were
unable to deviate, unless they all somehow changed together, because they were
united in their teleological goal: the sustaining of the whole.[27]
Cuvier stressed this point, writing that “none of these separate parts can
change their forms without a corresponding change on the other parts of the
same animal, and consequently each of these parts taken separately, indicates
all the other parts to which it has belonged.”[28]
This tight teleological interrelationship between the individual parts of an
organism precludes the possibility of any considerable variation, for if any
single part were to diverge from the overall telos, it would “fail to serve in an integrated fashion the end of
the organisms’ overall well-being.”[29]
Cuvier’s teleological approach to biology found much approval, particularly in
England where it was worked into the thriving and increasingly diverse natural
theology movement.[30]
Teleology in Evolutionary Biology
On November 24, 1859, Charles Darwin
published On the Origin of Species. It
was an instant bestseller, with all of the first edition copies being bought by
booksellers on the first day. This cannot be attributed to any unfamiliarity on
the part of his contemporaries, regarding evolutionary thinking.[31]
Thinkers such as Comte de Buffon and Denis Diderot had long since suggested,
albeit somewhat more speculatively than theoretically, that life could develop
and change through natural processes. Nevertheless, these suggestions were
taken up by the likes of Erasmus Darwin and Jean Baptiste Lamarck, who then
began to advance their own theories of transmutation.[32]
Yet, Darwin’s theory of natural selection was seen by his contemporaries to
have been different from these. Natural selection seemed to minimise the role
that any sort of purpose could play in the process, while simultaneously
emphasising the relevance of chance. As Timothy Shanahan has observed, “it
wasn’t so much Darwin’s advocacy of evolution that was novel or disturbing…
Rather, what was disconcerting was the idea that natural selection operating on
chance variations produced the diversity and apparent design in nature.”[33]
Since then, the apparent contradiction of purpose and chance has been the
source of much apprehension among religious believers.[34]
In the early nineteenth century,
William Paley’s approach to natural theology dominated much of the intellectual
landscape of biology. This approach, which emphasised the significance of
design in nature, was studied closely by Darwin at the University of Cambridge.
Initially Darwin seems to have been intrigued by Paley’s ideas; indeed, much of
his later writings were profoundly influenced by the work of the Anglican
clergyman.[35] Nevertheless,
he came to reject Paley’s approach. “The will of the Deity,” he wrote as early
as 1938, is “no explanation – it has not the character of a physical law &
is therefore utterly useless.”[36]
Darwin was adamant in his conviction that life did not arise or develop through
the interventions of an immaterial designer. Already by the 1820’s, it had
become common practice for geologists to reject any appeal to the supernatural
in their scientific explanations.[37]
Now, it was time for biology to follow their example, for Darwin was convinced
that there was no teleological impulse driving evolution.[38]
Likewise his ‘Bulldog’, Thomas Henry Huxley, held the view that “teleology, as
commonly understood, had received its deathblow at Mr. Darwin’s hands.”[39]
While comments such as these would seem
to suggest that both Huxley and Darwin thought all forms of teleology to be
undermined by natural selection, the reality is somewhat more nuanced. In
Huxley’s case, he was clearly referring to a specific approach to teleology
that had been undermined by Darwin’s work: Paley’s approach.[40]
He had argued that it was not necessary to invoke an external agent to explain
the apparent design in living things, for natural selection could operate at
such a level that it could counterfeit design.[41]
Yet, Huxley well knew that there were other approaches to teleology, besides
the one advanced by Paley, that remained unaffected by Darwin’s work. Indeed,
in a lecture given in 1887, while examining the deficiency of the ‘commonly
understood’ approach to teleology, Huxley made the point that evolution points
to a ‘wider teleology’ that is part of the deep structure of the universe.[42]
It is unclear what he was referring to, when speaking of a ‘wider teleology’; but,
it is clear that while rejecting some forms of teleology, Huxley did not extend
this rejection to all forms of teleology. Instead, he seems to have perceived
there to be some teleological impulse embedded in the structure of the
universe.
As with Huxley, it initially seems as
though Darwin also opposed teleology; for he strongly opposed the suggestions
of his advocate in America, Asa Gray, that evolutionary variations could be
directional so as to be designed. For Darwin, such issues were beyond the
capacity of science to adjudicate, so one could not justify making an
observation-based decision either way.[43]
Gray came to agree with this notion, concluding that such issues “must after
all rest mostly on faith.”[44]
Nevertheless, despite these declarations, Darwin advanced an understanding of
evolution that saw the history of life as an account of progress, from lower to
higher life forms. This notion of progress that he advanced was already
widespread in England during the Industrial Revolution, especially in
sociological circles. Darwin comments that “as natural selection works solely
by and for the good of each being, all corporeal and mental endowments will
tend to progress towards perfection.”[45]
Such a statement clearly resonates with a teleological understanding of
evolution, for Darwin undoubtedly believed that natural selection brought about
the development of life in an upward trend. It was his belief that natural
selection compelled life to progress because those that survived were better
than those who died, or as Michael Ruse has spelled out: “the winners overall
will be better than the losers.”[46]
Despite the popularity of these notions
of biological progress in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, in
contemporary biological circles they have largely been abandoned.[47]
This is not because scientists have necessarily stopped believing in biological
progress; rather, it is because of a shift that occurred in the philosophical
approach to science that emphasised the necessary objectivity of the scientific
observer.[48] For the
philosopher Karl Popper, values and beliefs had no place in science; instead,
he asserted that science should only consist of purely objective knowledge. According
to Popper, science should be “knowledge without a knower.”[49]
Such an approach to science, and to evolutionary biology, is clearly at odds
with the value-laden notions of progress that had been advanced in the
nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. Rather than a phenomenon that has
been observed in nature, the notion of progress has been seen to have been
imposed upon the scientific endeavour. David Zeigler has commented that
“progress is an entirely human concept that many humans have applied in this
case to a process decidedly not concerned with what humans are – or what they
think.”[50]
Accordingly, any reference to progress is considered to be thoroughly
unscientific.[51]
Likewise, it has often been argued that
this neo-Darwinian approach to evolutionary biology has undermined the notion
of teleology.[52] The
biologist C. S. Pittendrigh acknowledged the fact that processes in science can
be end-directed. Nevertheless, he argued that there is a difference between
end-directedness and teleology.[53]
‘Teleonomy’, as he termed this end-directedness, referred to the idea that
there may be underlying mechanisms that lead biological processes towards certain
ends. However, while conceding this point, he asserted that teleonomy rejects
the added notion that there must therefore be some sort of purpose or goal that
these processes are built upon. For Pittendrigh, biological processes may
arrive at certain ends, but that does not mean that they operate according to
some purpose.[54] In Chance & Necessity, the molecular
biologist Jacques Monod applied this notion of teleonomy to evolutionary
biology. For Monod evolution was teleonomical, in that it led to survival of
increasingly diverse organisms; but it was not teleological, for he saw no goal
or purpose to the process. Instead he saw “pure chance, absolutely free but
blind, at the very root of the stupendous edifice of evolution.”[55]
The question of teleology in biology is,
however, by no means resolved, for a number of biologists and philosophers have
emphasised the value of teleological explanations. The philosopher and
evolutionary biologist Francisco J. Ayala has argued that the notion of
teleology is essential to biology. He distinguishes between different
scientific disciplines such as physics and biology, by acknowledging that the
fall of a stone is not teleologically directed. But in biology he asserts that
“teleological explanations imply that the end result is the explanatory reason
for the existence of the object or
process which serves or leads to it. A teleological account of the gills of
fish implies that gills came to existence precisely because they serve for
respiration.”[56] Ayala
argues that teleology is indispensible to evolutionary biology for two reasons.
The first is that natural selection is established upon the teleological
principle of increasing reproductive efficiency. The second is that this
process then produces organs that have their own goals and purposes.[57]
Ernst Mayr, a philosopher of science, observed in 1988 that teleology had
become associated with obscurantism.[58]
Despite this, he made the observation, like Pittendrigh and Monod, that nature
is full of processes that are end-directed. However, he continued by criticising
the semantic struggles that such biologists go through when they attempt to
make teleological statements in a nonteleological manner. He writes that “the
use of so-called ‘teleological’ language by biologists is legitimate; it
neither implies a rejection of physicochemical explanation nor does it imply
noncausal explanation.”[59]
Despite their disputed status, teleological explanations undoubtedly have a
significant place in evolutionary biology. They open up new lines of inquiry
and provide a different perspective on old ones. Rather than being eliminated
from evolutionary biology, teleological explanations are expected to prosper.[60]
So far, this essay has emphasised the
historical significance of teleological explanations in science, and particularly
in evolutionary biology. By doing so, it has concluded that there have been a
number of approaches to understanding teleology, some neutral and some
theistic. Many of these approaches have been undermined by Darwinian evolution,
but not all. This essay has also examined a significant shift that occurred in
the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. This shift involved a desire to remove
notions such as progress and teleology from the study of evolutionary biology.
It was concluded that a major factor in this growing sentiment was the belief
that teleology was something that was imposed upon the scientific process. But
what if teleology were not imposed, but rather observed within the natural
world?
Evolution and Neutral Teleology:
Replaying the Tape of Life
It has already been argued that there
are processes at work within evolution that could be considered teleological.
The different parts of an organism appear to operate teleologically, for they
seem to operate according to the purpose that they serve. Also the mechanism
of evolution, natural selection, appears to be teleologically motivated for it
promotes a particular goal: reproductive efficiency. However, despite these conclusions, the
question of whether evolution is directed towards an end, or whether it has a specific purpose, is left entirely open. Indeed, while there are a number of
teleological cases within evolution, it is not necessary to infer that therefore the overall process of evolution is teleological. This essay
will now examine the evolutionary process and the significance of chance and
contingency on the one hand and purpose and directionality on the other, in
order to shed light on the teleological nature of evolution.
It is essential to Christianity that
nature be teleological, for Christian scriptures describe the world as being the
creation of a purposeful God.[61]
Not only this, but for a Christian the creation of human beings is seen as being
something of fundamental significance, for humans are God’s creation, made in
His image.[62] J.
Wentzel van Huyssteen emphasises that “being created in the image of God
highlights the extraordinary importance of human beings: humans are walking
representations of God, and as such are of exquisite value and importance”.[63]
This intimate connection that humans share with God has historically been
understood to indicate some trait or quality that humans are in possession of,
something deeply significant that sets them apart from the rest of creation.[64]
Recently, however, this exclusivist position has been criticised by biblical
scholars and philosophers.[65]
Nevertheless, regardless of whether humans are distinct from the rest of
creation or not, the value and importance of humanity remains a central tenet
in the Christian tradition.[66]
Indeed, Keith Ward even goes so far to assert that “however many billions of
galaxies there are, they will all exist as parts of a process whose goal is the
existence of human beings.”[67]
The point being made is that Christianity promotes a view of humanity that, at
the very least, emphasises their necessity. As Stephen J. Pope observes, “if
evolution is not part of a purposeful world, Christian convictions are false…”[68]
Darwinian evolution, however, seems to
suggest just that. It is frequently considered a random process, because of the
emphasis that is placed upon chance and contingency.[69]
Firstly, chance is one of the driving forces behind natural selection, for it
is through chance that beneficial mutations will occur in the genome of an
organism.[70] These
mutations do not appear according to some desire or requirement; rather, they
seemingly occur by accident.[71]
Like chance, contingent events also seem to undermine the idea of a purposeful
creation, suggesting that there is no underlying plan for the universe. Contingency
emphasises the fact that natural selection occurs when traits are selected in
response to environmental pressures. For example, if a drought were to suddenly
occur, the efficiency with which an organism manages water would be critical.
But if there was an abundance of water, then other characteristics might count as
being more important. The point is that there is no absolute superior or
inferior adaptation; the environment determines what is good and what is bad.[72]
Of course, these external events are not necessarily uncaused; rather, they are
seen as contingent because they appear to occur contrary to any foreseeable
purpose or plan.
These two approaches seem to be
irreconcilable. The Christian cannot agree with George Gaylord Simpson’s remark
that “man is the result of a purposeless and natural process that did not have
him in mind.”[73] This is because, as humans, “we are the
focus of God’s love and care and attention. We are the beings for whom He
suffered on the Cross. All of this means that for the Christian we are not
contingent beings… We are the focus and purpose of creation.”[74]
But, contingency and chance must be integrated into a Christian understanding
of humanity if these two positions are to be reconciled.
The late Stephen Jay Gould devoted much
of his attention to discussing the implications of contingency and chance in
the process of evolution. It was his view that organisms evolved the traits
they did simply from the “luck of the draw”.[75]
His view of chance and evolution was fundamentally shaped by his work on the
Burgess Shale rock formations in the Canadian Rockies, and the Cambrian fauna
found within them.[76]
Of the great diversity of organisms found in the shale, only four groups of
organisms, arranged by the similarity in their anatomical frameworks, survived.[77]
Gould stressed the point that the selection of these four anatomical
frameworks, over the others, was largely a result of contingent circumstances.
If the circumstances had been different, he argues, then this would have a significant
consequence for the fauna alive today. Indeed, referring to the extinction of
dinosaurs, Gould remarked that “since dinosaurs were not moving toward markedly
larger brains, and since such a prospect may lie outside the capabilities of
reptilian design, we must assume that consciousness would not have evolved on
our planet if a cosmic catastrophe had not claimed the dinosaurs as victims. In
an entirely literal sense, we owe our existence, as large and reasoning
mammals, to our lucky stars.“[78]
For Gould, the sheer number of contingent events that must have taken place in
order to allow for the arrival of human beings seems to undermine the notion
that evolution is purposeful. Despite his declaration that there is no conflict
between science and religion, he writes in a typically forthright way of
natural history being like a tape that can be rewound and replayed again and
again.[79]
“Replay the tape a million times from a Burgess beginning,” he asserts, “and I
doubt that anything like Homo sapiens would ever evolve again.”[80]
For Gould, it is largely down to luck that humans are alive today.
Nevertheless, it is also important to
recognise that there was an agenda to much of Gould’s work. It was a great
concern to him that Darwinian evolution was being treated as a line of
progress, where the complexity of species was bound to increase until natural
selection gave rise to humans. Instead of seeing the evolution of life as being
similar to a ladder, with humans at the top, he envisioned an oddly shaped bush
with no real top or bottom.[81]
A similar picture he utilised was of a tree. He did not cast humans in the most
important position, but instead saw them as a “tiny twig on an improbable
branch of a contingent limb on a fortunate tree.”[82]
Gould’s point is, perhaps, expressed most ironically in the words of Mark
Twain: “God’s noblest work? Man. Who found it out? Man.”[83]
To view the evolution of life as leading inexorably towards humanity, without
biological justification and resting instead on prejudice, was seen by Gould to
be the height of human egocentricity.[84]
However Gould did make the concession that,
over time, natural selection has produced species that are more complex and
intelligent. He did not attribute this pattern of development to anything
teleological in the evolutionary process, but instead referred to something
that he termed the “left wall” phenomenon.[85]
In describing this phenomenon, he used the story of a drunken man as an
example. Staggering down a path beside a street on a Saturday night, he is
walking without any purpose or sense of direction. Yet every time he stumbles
to the left he hits a wall of buildings. In this scenario, it would only be a
matter of time before he fell to his right and would find himself lying on the
street. Gould argued that the same is true of evolution. Evolution produces
greater complexity because there is no room for the development of more simple
organisms; all the niches have already been filled. So evolution drunkenly
meanders towards greater complexity. Accordingly, the “vaunted progress of life
is really a random motion away from simple beginnings, not directed impetus
toward any inherently advantageous complexity.”[86]
In part, Gould intended his arguments
to correct what he saw as an arrogant view, that human beings are a necessary
result of evolution. Yet Richard Dawkins, an evolutionary biologist with no
motivation to promote the significance of humanity, has argued that evolution
can be described as progressive. For Dawkins, natural selection leads to
competition among organisms. The group that is better adapted to their specific
environment will outcompete the group that is not. This process will continue,
leading to the progressive accumulation of characteristics to improve the
fitness of an organism to its environment.[87]
This evolutionary ‘arms race’ could be considered to lead eventually to the
emergence of humanity.[88]
However, this presupposes that the environment does not shift over time, for as
has already been observed, it is the environment that will determine the
superior adaptation. Dawkins emphasises the notion of progress in natural
selection, while Gould emphasises contingency; but both overstate the influence
that each factor has on the evolutionary process.[89]
Evolution must instead be understood as the result of the interaction between
contingency and progress, between random and non-random.[90]
As Ayala observes, evolution is a “’selecting’ process which picks up adaptive
combinations because these reproduce more effectively and thus become
established in populations. These adaptive combinations constitute, in turn, new
levels of organization upon which the mutation (random) plus selection
(non-random or directional) process again operates.”[91]
Despite these criticisms, perhaps the
most thorough critique of Gould’s position is made by Simon Conway Morris. Like
Gould, Conway Morris is a palaeontologist. Both men worked on the organisms
found within the Burgess Shale rock formation. However, Conway Morris came to a
radically different conclusion concerning the nature of directionality and
purpose within evolution. While Gould was impressed by the seeming randomness
and contingency in the evolutionary process, Conway Morris was impressed by the
cases of convergence.[92]
He understood convergent evolution, or “the recurrent tendency of biological
organization to arrive at the same ‘solution’ to a particular need’”, to point
to something profoundly significant about the development of life.[93]
Conway Morris’s approach to evolutionary
directionality should be distinguished from other quite different approaches,
such as one advanced by Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, who suggested that there
was some sort of mysterious impulse running through the evolutionary process
that led to the development of humans.[94]
Such a position as this would undermine the significance of chance and
contingency within evolution, which Conway Morris does not seek to do. Nevertheless,
while he does not place as much emphasis on these processes as Gould, he also
recognises their significance.[95]
For Conway Morris, chance is the search engine that “navigates the
combinatorial immensities of biological ‘hyperspace’.”[96]
Indeed, when he uses another metaphor of a boat in the middle of an
“essentially inhospitable ocean of maladaptivity,” chance is the motor that
powers the boat in search of “islands of stability.”[97]
Such a metaphor affirms the notion advanced by Gould, that there are many ways
that an organism might evolve that are theoretically possible. However, Conway
Morris concludes that instead of exploring these theoretical possibilities,
organisms are far more likely to converge on the same solution.[98]
This is because the evolutionary process is constrained by biological constraints
that limit the process of adaptation.[99]
Nevertheless, despite the fact that
there are a limited number of end-points that organisms are constrained to
evolve into, the emergence of humans is still highly unlikely. But it is
important to recognise that evolution often follows a sequence of steps, where
“once one stage is achieved, other things then become so much more likely.”[100]
In contrast to Gould, Conway Morris’s conclusion is that, with the emergence eukaryotes,
the emergence of animals becomes far more likely. Then as animals emerge, one
would expect to soon see a developing nervous system. As organisms continue to
converge on these precursors to humanity, it becomes far more likely that
humans would arise. Indeed, once an organism has a nervous system, to develop a
primitive form of intelligence would be much simpler to develop and quite
advantageous.[101]
Responding to Gould, Conway Morris concludes that “however many times we re-run
the tape, we will still end up with much the same result.”[102]
It would be difficult to find a more
intellectually robust and scientifically grounded alternative to Gould than
Conway Morris’s approach.[103]
The understanding of evolution advanced by Conway Morris does not undermine the
significance of chance and contingency, these factors still have a part to play
in the evolutionary process. However, by emphasising the biological constraints
that lead to convergence, he affirms the notion that there is a directional element
to evolution, a conclusion that many evolutionists would be averse to.[104]
In recent years though, the significance of directionality has been discussed far
more openly and has received far more support amongst intellectuals.[105]
But does this directionality necessarily demonstrate that evolution is
teleological? Conway Morris certainly seems to think so, for he asserts that convergence
shows there to be “a deeper structure to life, a metaphorical landscape across
which evolution must necessarily navigate.”[106]
Such a declaration resonates strongly with the assertion made by Huxley that
evolution points to a ‘wider teleology’ embedded in the deep structure of the
universe.[107] Both positions
acknowledge evolution as the vehicle of creation, but both also point out that
there is something deeper, beneath the evolutionary process. There is an end
point, a destination which evolution is seeking, and evolution is merely the
vehicle that “provides the means to get from A to B.”[108]
But what is the teleological
significance of Conway Morris’s approach to evolution? Teleological statements
and explanations are commonly rejected by the scientific community for a number
of reasons. One reason is that teleology is frequently understood to imply a
theological or metaphysical approach to evolutionary biology. Another reason is
that a teleological approach to evolutionary biology is scientifically
unverifiable, and is rather the result of specific assumptions being imposed
upon the scientific process.[109]
If these reasons were necessarily so, then teleological statements and
explanations would rightly be excluded from evolutionary biology. But Conway
Morris’s approach to evolution raises the question of teleology, not based upon
a priori assumptions, but instead
based upon a posteriori observations.
Also, Conway Morris’s approach does not impose a specific theological or
metaphysical agenda upon the scientific process, but instead remains neutral in
these issues. These common objections to teleology being included in
evolutionary explanations do not hold, “if some kind of teleology is discerned
within, not imposed upon, the biological process.”[110]
Thus, Conway Morris’s emphasis on the phenomenon of convergence suggests that a
theologically neutral understanding of teleology is consistent with the
evolutionary process.
Evolution and Theistic Teleology: God
Playing Dice
It has already been argued that
evolutionary biology supports a theologically neutral, teleological approach to
the development of life. This essay will now turn to the question of whether a
theistic understanding of teleology is undermined by evolutionary biology.
There have been a number of theistic approaches to teleology in history that
have been undermined by evolutionary thinking, most significantly the
‘watchmaker’ God advanced by Paley.[111]
Nevertheless, when Paley’s approach to theistic teleology was undermined by
Darwinian evolution, a common response was to recast God in the same position,
just one level higher up, as the architect of the evolutionary process. His
role as designer did not change at all, rather instead of designing human beings
as a separate creation, God utilised the process of evolution for this end.[112]
An example of this can be seen in the writings of the clergyman and historian
Charles Kingsley, who rejoiced that Darwin had revealed how “we knew of old
that God was so wise that He could make all things: but behold, He is so much
wiser than even that, that He can make all things make themselves.”[113]
The picture that Kingsley develops, in appropriating evolution into his
Christian worldview, is of a God who endows creation with the potential to
develop. Both the initial creation and the subsequent developments are equally seen
by Kingsley to be the purposeful creation of God.[114]
There is an important point to be made in emphasising God’s purposes in the
developments of evolution, for while Conway Morris’s approach to evolution
compliments a theistic worldview, its theistic neutrality means that it is
equally open to a deistic interpretation.[115]
However, it is essential to Christianity that God is not seen as simply setting
things in motion to then let universe run, but rather that God continues to be
working in creation.[116]
While Kingsley’s slogan has rhetorical value, it is far too general to actually
explain how God could act in and through the process of evolution. To approach
this question, this essay will first consider how God might be understood to
interact with His creation, before secondly exploring the possibility of divine
action in the evolutionary process.
A Christian understanding of creation
maintains that God existed before his creation and that he is separate from it,
having created it from nothing.[117]
Nevertheless God is also seen to act within creation, with the universe being
dependent upon His sustaining action for its existence. Thus, God is envisioned
as being both transcendent and immanent.[118]
God’s transcendence is not called into question by the predominance of chance
and contingency in the evolutionary process; instead, it is His immanence and
intentionality in the creating and sustaining of the world that is challenged.
The question raised by this apparent inconsistency concerns how an intentional
God could act within a process that seems to allow him no room to manoeuver.
Conway Morris’s emphasis on the biological constraints within evolution is no
different, for these constraints operate as part of the structure of the
universe, limiting the number of possible adaptations an organism could evolve
into. Both of these approaches emphasise a naturalistic understanding of the
evolutionary process, implying that God need not be involved. This seems to
dispute the notion that God could have the capacity to act in a meaningful way
to influence the creation of the universe, beyond what a deistic God could do.
In this essay, the restriction of God’s
action in the creative process has largely been assumed to be a negative
outcome, as it appears to limit the extent to which teleology may be imposed by
the creator upon His creation. But, the contingencies and chance events in
evolution may actually be a necessary part of God’s plan. For, hypothetically,
if God did create the world through a thoroughly deterministic process, without
any element of chance or contingency at all, his creation would undoubtedly be
teleological. However, it would be no different from Paley’s watch: an
instrument or a machine, and nothing else. This does not align with a Christian
understanding of God’s creative action, nor His desire to enter into a
relationship with humanity, because this would leave little room for a
responsive and interactive relationship.[119]
On the other hand, if God were said to act indirectly in the world, as a
primary cause, through the operation of his secondary causes, then God could be
seen as acting through the process of evolution.[120]
Thomas F. Tracy remarks that “we can imagine God designing the laws of nature
(both deterministic and probabilistic) to produce an evolutionary process that
explores a bounded space of possibility… On this account, our coming to be
within the natural order can be attributed to God’s action, but not to God’s
specific intention.”[121]
In this unfolding of life, as God draws creation to himself, so relationship is
woven into the fabric of the world. This approach to teleology is consistent
with the scientific understanding of evolution advanced by Conway Morris.
The picture presented so far is
consistent with Christian theology. But, if it were the only case of God’s
interaction with His creation, this picture would still resemble a remodelled
deism. In such a picture, God’s providence is restricted to his act of
creation, for he is seen to enact specific events, but not take part in them.[122]
Nevertheless, a number of scientists and theologians have proposed various
ideas about how God could act more directly in evolution.[123]
The scientist and theologian John Polkinghorne, for example, has recently
suggested that God would be able to influence the various cases of
indeterminacy that occur at the quantum level, so as to bring about a desired
end result.[124] This
view understands God’s interactions in a temporal sense, as being constrained
to particular actions at particular times.[125]
The unknown factors in the process of evolution, such as contingency and chance,
would be seen as an obstruction to God’s work rather than a source of
liberation. A disturbing consideration, however, would be that God, as a
temporal being, would carry out providential incursions into the evolutionary
process without full knowledge of the repercussions of such actions.
Polkinghorne’s view of God as a
temporal being, acting in the evolutionary process at the quantum level, is a
valid theistic approach to understanding teleology. Nevertheless, it assumes
inadequacy in how God may intervene. On the other hand, if God were understood
to be outside of time, then these limitations would be avoided. For an
‘atemporal’ God, “creation continues at every moment, and each moment has the
same relation of dependency on the Creator. God transcends the world…Yet the
Creator is also immanent…sustaining it in being. God knows the world in the act
of creating it and thus knows the cosmic past, present, and future in a single
unmediated grasp.”[126]
If God is understood to be atemporal, then the role of chance and contingency
in evolution need not be undermined. In this regard, chance does not undermine
purpose, and contingency does not undermine teleology, for the outcome is
already known.[127]
To allow God to act in an atemporal way permits a recasting of the questions
being posed. Chance and contingency may mean more to God than the random events
as they are experienced by His creation. No longer is it necessary for these
factors to be understood as deterministic forces, restricting how God may or
may not act. Instead, they can be considered a vital part of the interactive
process between the Creator and his creation.
Conclusion
Teleology has had a long and at times
turbulent relationship with the sciences. Despite the claim that evolutionary
biology can have no correspondence with teleology, it has remained a kind of
philosophical ‘elephant in the room’, that refuses to dwindle away. A colleague
of Jacques Monod, Francois Jacob, has likened the relationship to that shared
between a gentleman and his mistress: someone that “biologists could not do
without, but did not care to be seen with in public.”[128]
Much of the stigma associated with teleology comes from its presumed
unscientific nature; nevertheless, Simon Conway Morris’s approach to
evolutionary biology is both scientific and teleological. In this sense, his
approach represents a new and coherent perspective in the relationship between
the two.
The question running throughout this essay has been concerned with whether the contingent and chance-like processes inherent in Darwinian evolution undermine the belief that human beings have been purposefully created. I have argued that contingency and chance do not necessarily undermine the belief that humans have been purposefully created. In doing this I have conceded that some, though not all, approaches to teleology have been challenged by evolutionary biology. Nevertheless, I have sought to argue that evolutionary biology supports a theologically neutral, teleological approach to the development of life, by exploring the notion of directionality in the work of Simon Conway Morris. On top of this claim, I have also argued that evolutionary biology does not undermine a theistic understanding of teleology. Indeed, if God is viewed as a temporal being then he is able to interact with the evolutionary process at the quantum level, and if God is understood to be an atemporal being, then chance and contingency do not represent a problem, for their outcomes would already be known. Thus, the contingent and chance-like processes inherent in Darwinian evolution do not undermine purpose and teleology.
The question running throughout this essay has been concerned with whether the contingent and chance-like processes inherent in Darwinian evolution undermine the belief that human beings have been purposefully created. I have argued that contingency and chance do not necessarily undermine the belief that humans have been purposefully created. In doing this I have conceded that some, though not all, approaches to teleology have been challenged by evolutionary biology. Nevertheless, I have sought to argue that evolutionary biology supports a theologically neutral, teleological approach to the development of life, by exploring the notion of directionality in the work of Simon Conway Morris. On top of this claim, I have also argued that evolutionary biology does not undermine a theistic understanding of teleology. Indeed, if God is viewed as a temporal being then he is able to interact with the evolutionary process at the quantum level, and if God is understood to be an atemporal being, then chance and contingency do not represent a problem, for their outcomes would already be known. Thus, the contingent and chance-like processes inherent in Darwinian evolution do not undermine purpose and teleology.
[1] John Hedley Brooke, Science and Religion: Some Historical
Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014); Ronald L.
Numbers,ed., Galileo Goes To Jail and
Other Myths about Science and Religion (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 2010).
[2] Ephesians 1:4, NRSV.
[3] Neil A. Manson, God and Design: The Teleological Argument
and Modern Science (London: Routledge, 2003), 1; Denis Walsh, “Teleology,”
in The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of
Biology, ed. by Michael Ruse (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 113;
Ian G. Barbour, Religion and Science:
Historical and Contemporary Issues (New York: Harper One, 1997), 360.
[4] Walsh, “Teleology,” 113; John
Hedley Brooke, Science and Religion: Some
Historical Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2014),
261-262; William Paley, Natural Theology
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006).
[5] Alister E. McGrath, A Fine-Tuned Universe: The Quest for God in
Science and Theology (Louisville: Westminster John Knox Press, 2009), 184.
[6] Paul F. Lurquin and Linda
Stone, Evolution and Religious Creation
Myths: How Scientists Respond (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007), 53.
[7] David Hanke, “Teleology: the
explanation that bedevils biology,” in Explanations:
Styles of Explanations in Science, ed. by John Cornwell (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2004), 145.
[8] Stephen C. Meyer, Signature in the Cell: DNA and the Evidence
for Intelligent Design (New York: Harper One, 2009), 349-359; Jerry
Bergman, “Affirmations of God’s Existence from Design in Nature,” Answers in Depth 7 (2012): https://answersingenesis.org/is-god-real/affirmations-of-gods-existence-from-design-in-nature/; Eugenie C. Scott and
Nicholas J Matzke, “Biological design in science classrooms,” PNAS 104 (2007): 8669-8676; Manson, God and Design, xv.
[9] Alister E. McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine: Evolutionary
Thought and Natural Theology (Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2011), 188-189.
[10] Monte Ransome Johnson, Aristotle on Teleology (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2006), 1; Robert J. Richards, “Michael Ruse’s Design for
Living,” Journal of the History of
Biology 37 (2004): 27.
[11] Richards, “Michael Ruse’s
Design for Living,” 27.
[12] John M. Cooper, “Aristotle on
Natural Teleology,” in Nature and the
Good: Essays on Ancient Philosophy, ed. John M. Cooper (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2004), 107-129; Stephen Gaukroger, The Emergence of a Scientific Culture:
Science and the Shaping of Modernity 1210-1685 (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
2013), 337-339.
[13] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 189; Bruce D. Marshall, “Quod Scit Una
Uetula: Aquinas on the Nature of Theology,” in The Theology of Thomas Aquinas, ed. Rik Van Nieuwenhove and Joseph
Wawrykow (Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 2010), 7; David C. Lindberg,
“Medieval Science and Religion,” in Science
and Religion: A Historical Introduction, ed. Gary B. Ferngren (Baltimore:
The John Hopkins University Press, 2002), 67-69.
[14] Marjorie Grene, “Aristotle
and Modern Biology,” Journal of the
History of Ideas 33 (1972): 395-424.
[15] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 189.
[16] Gaukroger, The Emergence of a Scientific Culture,
228-322; Margaret J. Osler, “Mechanical Philosophy,” in Science and Religion: A Historical Introduction, ed. Gary B.
Ferngren (Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press, 2002), 143-144.
[17] Janet Browne, “Noah’s Flood,
the Ark, and the Shaping of Early Modern Natural History,” in When Science & Christianity Meet,
ed. David C. Lindberg and Ronald L. Numbers (Chicago: The University of Chicago
Press, 2008), 129; John Hedley Brooke, “Natural Theology,” in Science and Religion: A Historical
Introduction, ed. Gary B. Ferngren (Baltimore: The John Hopkins University
Press, 2002), 163-164.
[18] Brooke, Science and Religion, 261-276; Don Bates, “Machine ex Deo: William
Harvey and the Meaning of Instrument,” Journal
of the History of Ideas 61 (2001): 577; Brian Garrett, “Vitalism and
Teleology in the Natural Philosophy of Nehemiah Grew (1641-1712),” British Journal for the History of Science
36 (2003): 63.
[19] Timothy Lenoir, The Strategy of Life: Teleology and
Mechanics in Nineteenth Century German Biology (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1989), 112-194.
[20] Brooke, Science and Religion, 276-284; Brooke, “Natural Theology,” 169.
[21] Brooke, Science and Religion,
280.
[22] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 190.
[23] Michael Ruse, “Teleology:
Yesterday, Today, and Tomorrow?” Studies
in History and Philosophy of Science 31 (2000): 214.
[24] Quoted in William Coleman, Georges Cuvier, Zoologist: A Study in the
History of Evolution Theory (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1964),
42.
[25]Jon F. Harrison, et al., Ecological and Environmental Physiology of
Insects (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012), 71-84.
[26] Ruse, “Teleology: Yesterday,
Today, and Tomorrow?” 215; Michael Ruse, Monad
to Man: The Concept of Progress in Evolutionary Biology (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press, 1996), 84-89.
[27] Ruse, “Teleology: Yesterday,
Today, and Tomorrow?” 215-216; Ruse, Monad
to Man, 85.
[28] Georges Cuvier, Essay on the Theory of the Earth, trans.
R. Kerr (Edinburgh: William Blackwood, 1822), 90-91.
[29] Ruse, “Teleology: Yesterday,
Today, and Tomorrow?” 215.
[30] Ibid., 216; Brooke, “Natural
Theology,” 169-170.
[31] Peter J. Bowler, Evolution: The History of an Idea
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 2009), 48-140.
[32] Peter J. Bowler, “Evolution,”
in Science and Religion: A Historical
Introduction, ed. Gary B. Ferngren (Baltimore: The John Hopkins University
Press, 2002), 220-222.
[33] Timothy Shanahan, The Evolution of Darwinism: Selection,
Adaptation, and Progress in Evolutionary Biology (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2004), 14.
[34] David Fergusson, “Darwin and Providence,” in Theology After
Darwin, ed. Michael S. Northcott and R.J. Berry. (Milton Keynes:
Paternoster, 2009), 78; John Hedley Brooke, “Genesis and the Scientists:
Dissonance among the Harmonizers,” in Reading
Genesis After Darwin, ed. Stephen C. Barton and David Wilkinson (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2009), 100-101; James R. Moore, The Post-Darwinian Controversies (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1979), 245-250.
[35] David N. Livingstone,
“Re-Placing Darwinism and Christianity,” in When
Science & Christianity Meet, ed. David C. Lindberg and Ronald L. Numbers
(Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2008), 188; Thomas Dixon, Science and Religion: A Very Short
Introduction (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 64.
[36] Quoted in Ronald L. Numbers,
“Science without God,” in When Science
& Christianity Meet, ed. David C. Lindberg and Ronald L. Numbers
(Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 2008), 279.
[37] Ibid., 278.
[38] Michael Ruse, The Philosophy of Human Evolution
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2012), 103.
[39] Thomas H. Huxley, Lay Sermons, Addresses, and Reviews
(London: Macmillan, 1870), 301.
[40] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 186.
[41] Brooke, “Natural Theology,”
171-172. A more contemporary example of Huxley’s criticism can be found in
Richard Dawkins, The Blind Watchmaker:
Why the Evidence of Evolution Reveals a Universe Without Design (New York:
W.W. Norton, 1986).
[42] Francis Darwin, ed., The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin
(London: John Murray, 1887), 201; See also McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 186-187 and Celia Deanne-Drummond,
“Plumbing the Depths: A Recovery of Natural Law and Natural Wisdom in the
Context of Debates about Evolutionary Purpose,” in The Deep Structure of Biology: Is Convergence Sufficiently Ubiquitous
to Give a Directional Signal?, ed. Simon Conway Morris (Conshohocken:
Templeton Press, 2008), 195-217.
[43] Ruse, The Philosophy of Human Evolution, 103.
[44] The Letters of Asa Gray: Volume 2, ed. Jane Gray (Boston: Houghton
Mifflin, 1868), 562. See also Phil Dowe, Galileo,
Darwin, and Hawking: The Interplay of Science, Reason, and Religion (Grand
Rapids: William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2005), 130-131.
[45] Charles Darwin, On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural
Selection, or the Preservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life
(London: John Murray, 1859), 489.
[46] Ruse, The Philosophy of Human Evolution, 107; Bowler, Evolution, 146. See also Shanahan, The Evolution of Darwinism, 285-294 for
an examination Darwin’s beliefs concerning evolutionary progress.
[47] Ruse, The Philosophy of Human Evolution, 110-111.
[48] Ibid., 112.
[49] Karl Popper, Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary
Approach (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1979), 109.
[50] David Zeigler, Evolution: Components & Mechanisms
(London: Elsevier, 2014), 171.
[51] Ruse, The Philosophy of Human Evolution, 112-113. This is not to say that
scientists do not hold the view that evolution is progressive, for
distinguished scientists such as Julian Huxley and Edward O. Wilson have both
supported such views. Rather, this is to say that the majority of scientists
who hold to the notion of progress do not do so on account of their
understanding of science. See Edward O. Wilson, The Diversity of Life (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992),
187; Julian Huxley, “Introduction,” in Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, The Phenomenon of Man (London: Collins,
1959), 11-28.
[52] Steve Stewart-Williams, Darwin, God, and the Meaning of Life: How
Evolutionary Theory Undermines Everything You Thought You Knew (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2010), 188-198; Jacques Monod Chance & Necessity: An Essay on the Natural Philosophy of Modern
Biology (New York: Vintage Books, 1972), 112-113; McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 190.
[53] Colin S. Pittendrigh,
“Adaptation, Natural Selection, and Behavior,” in Behavior and Evolution, ed. Anne Roe and George Gaylord Simpson
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1958), 394.
[54] Pittendrigh, “Adaptation,
Natural Selection, and Behavior,”390-416;
Alister E. McGrath, Science &
Religion: A New Introduction (Malden: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010), 164-165.
[55] Monod, Chance and Necessity, 112.
[56] Francisco J. Ayala,
“Teleological Explanations in Evolutionary Biology,” Philosophy of Science 37(1970): 12.
[57] Ayala, “Teleological
Explanations in Evolutionary Biology,” 1-15; McGrath, Science & Religion, 165; McGrath, A Fine-Tuned Universe, 187.
[58] Ernst Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology:
Observations of an Evolutionist (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
1988), 41.
[59] Ernst Mayr, Evolution and the Diversity of Life:
Selected Essays (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1997), 402.
[60] Ruse, “Teleology: Yesterday,
Today, and Tomorrow?” 231; Michael Ruse, Science
and Spirituality: Making Room for Faith in the Age of Science (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2014), 140-146.
[61] Genesis 1:1-2:25; Psalm 8:5; Job 38:1-42:6; Hebrews 2:7.
[62] Genesis 1:27.
[63]
J. Wentzel Van Huyssteen, Alone in the
World? Human Uniqueness in Science and Theology (Cambridge: William B.
Eerdmans Publishing Company, 2012), 121.
[64] David
Clough, “All God’s Creatures: Reading Genesis on Human and Nonhuman Animals,”
in Reading Genesis After Darwin, ed.
by Stephen C. Barton and David Wilkinson. (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2009), 145-161.
[65] David
L. Clough, On Animals: Volume 1 Systematic
Theology (London: T&T Clark, 2012); Clough, “All God’s Creatures,” 156;
Gijsbert van den Brink, “Are We Still Special? Evolution and Human Dignity,” Neue Zeitschrift fur Systematische Theologie
und Religionsphilosophie 53 (2011): 321; Ernst M. Conradie, An Ecological Christian Anthropology
(Aldershot: Ashgate Publishers, 2005), 80; David S. Cunningham, “The Way of All
Flesh: Re-Thinking the Imago Dei,” in Creaturely
Theology: On God, Humans and other Animals, ed. by Celia Deanne-Drummond
and David Clough. (London: SCM Press, 2009), 117.
[66] Alister E. McGrath, Christian Theology: An Introduction (Malden:
Blackwell Publishing, 2007), 360-362; Psalm 8:1-9;
[67] Keith Ward, God, Faith and the New Millenium
(Oxford: Oneworld, 1998), 22.
[68] Stephen J. Pope, Human Evolution and Christian Ethics
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2011), 111.
[69] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 192.
[70] John Tyler Bonner, Randomness in Evolution (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 2013), 4-7.
[71] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 192; Cynthia Crysdale and Neil Ormerod, Creator God, Evolving World
(Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2013), 36-38. See also George Gaylord Simpson, The Meaning of Evolution: A Study of the
History of Life and of Its Significance for Man (New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1967).
[72] Michael Ruse, Can a Darwinian be a Christian? The
Relationship between Science and Religion (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2001), 83.
[73] Simpson, The meaning of evolution, 344-345.
[74] Ruse, Can a Darwinian be a Christian?, 83.
[75] Stephen Jay Gould, Eight Little Piggies (New York: Penguin,
1993), 77.
[76] Stephen Jay Gould, Wonderful Life: The Burgess Shale and the
Nature of History (New York: W.W. Norton, 1989).
[77] Stephen Jay Gould, “The
Disparity of the Burgess Shale Arthropod Fauna and the Limits of Cladistic
Analysis: Why We Must Strive to Quantify Morphospace,” Paleobiology 17 (1991): 412.
[78] Gould, Wonderful Life, 318.
[79] See Stephen Jay Gould, Rocks of Ages: Science and Religion in the
Fullness of Life (New York: The Ballantine Publishing Group, 1999) for
Gould’s defence of ‘non-overlapping magisteria’.
[80] Ibid., 289.
[81] Stephen Jay Gould, “Bushes
and Ladders,” in Ever since Darwin:
Reflections in Natural History (New York: W.W. Norton, 1977), 56-62.
[82] Gould, Wonderful Life, 291.
[83] Mark Twain, Collected tales, sketches, speeches, and
essays, vol. II: 1891-1910 (New York: Library of America, 1992), 943.
[84] Stephen Jay Gould, The panda’s thumb: More reflections in
natural history (New York: Norton, 1980), 136.
[85] Stephen Jay Gould, Life’s Grandeur: The Spread of Excellence
from Plato to Darwin (New York: Random House, 1997), 167-171.
[86] Ibid., 173.
[87] Richard Dawkins and John R.
Krebs, “Arms races between and within species,” Proceedings of the Royal Society of London, Series B: Biological
Sciences 205 (1979): 489-511.
[88] Ruse, Philosophy of Human Evolution, 115.
[89] Pope, Human Evolution and Christian Ethics, 115.
[90] Theodosius Dobzhansky,
“Chance and Creativity in Evolution,” in Studies
in the Philosophy of Biology, ed. Francisco J. Ayala and Theodosius
Dobzhansky (London: Macmillan, 1974), 309-311.
[91] Francisco J. Ayala, “Darwin’s
Devolution: Design without a Designer,” in Evolutionary
and Molecular Biology: Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action, ed. Robert
John Russell, William R. Stoeger, SJ, and Francisco J. Ayala (Vatican City
State: Vatican Observatory Publications, 1998), 106.
[92] Simon Conway Morris, The Crucible of Creation: The Burgess Shale
and the Rise of Animals (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998).
[93] Simon Conway Morris, Life’s Solution: Inevitable Humans in a
Lonely Universe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), xii.
[94] Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, Le phénomène humain (Paris: Editions du
Seuil, 1955).
[95] See also Arthur Peacocke, Creation and the World of Science
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1979), 94.
[96] Conway Morris, Life’s Solution, 127.
[97] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 193. See also Conway Morris, Life’s Solution, 1-21, 127.
[98] Conway Morris, Life’s Solution, xii.
[99] See for example George R.
McGhee, The Geometry of Evolution:
Adaptive Landscapes and Theoretical Morphospaces (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2006), 108-151; R.J.P. Williams and J.J.R. Frausto da Silva,
“Evolution Was Chemically Constrained,” in Journal
of Theoretical Biology 220 (2003): 323; Bonner, Randomness in Evolution, 120.
[100] Conway Morris, Life’s Solution, 18.
[101] Conway Morris, Life’s Solution, xii; Simon Conway
Morris, “Evolution and the inevitability of intelligent life,” in The Cambridge Companion to Science and
Religion, ed. Peter Harrison (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010),
154-165.
[102] Conway Morris, “Evolution and
the inevitability of intelligent life,” 150.
[103] Pope, Human Evolution and Christian Ethics, 119; Andrew Steane, Faithful to Science: The Role of Science in
Religion (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014), 67.
[104] Zeigler, Evolution, 171-174; George Gaylord Simpson, This View of Life (New York: Harcourt, Brace, & World, Inc.,
1964).
[105] Christian De Duve, Vital dust: Life as a cosmic imperative
(New York: Basic Books, 1995); William R. Stoeger, “The Immanent Directionality
of the Evolutionary Process, and Its Relationship to Teleology,” in Evolutionary and Molecular Biology:
Scientific Perspectives on Divine Action, ed. Robert John Russell, William
R. Stoeger, SJ, and Francisco J. Ayala (Vatican City State: Vatican Observatory
Publications, 1998), 163-190.
[106] Simon Conway Morris,
“Darwin’s Compass: How Evolution Discovers the Song of Creation,” Science and Christian Belief 18 (2006):
16.
[107] Darwin, ed., The Life and Letters of Charles Darwin,
201.
[108] Simon Conway Morris,
“Creation and Evolutionary Convergence,” in The
Blackwell Companion to Science and Christianity, ed. J.B. Stump and Alan G.
Padgett (Malden: Blackwell Publishing, 2012), 261.
[109] Mayr, Toward a New Philosophy of Biology, 39-41.
[110] McGrath, Darwinism and the Divine, 190.
[111] Paley, Natural Theology.
[112] Thomas F. Tracy, “Divine
Purpose and Evolutionary Processes,” Zygon
48 (2013): 454.
[113] Charles Kingsley, Westminster Sermons (London: Macmillan,
1874), v.
[114] Ibid, xxv. This view has been
subsequently developed in Jurgen Moltmann, God
in Creation: An Ecological Doctrine of Creation (London: SCM Press, 1985),
9.
[115] Morris, “Creation and
Evolutionary Convergence,” 266.
[116] John 5:17.
[117] Genesis 1:1; John 1:1-5.
[118] Tracy, “Divine Purpose and
Evolutionary Processes,” 456.
[119] Genesis 2:19-20; John
1:10-13; Revelation 3:20.
[120] Tracy, “Divine Purpose and
Evolutionary Processes,” 456-459.
[121] Ibid., 458.
[122] Ibid., 459.
[123] Ernan McMullin, “Cosmic
Purpose and the Contingency of Human Evolution,” Zygon 48 (2013): 352.
[124] John Polkinghorne, Belief in God in an Age of Science (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1998), 57-75.
[125] McMullin, “Cosmic Purpose and
the Contingency of Human Evolution,” 355.
[126] Ibid., 355.
[127] Ibid., 359.
[128] Quoted in McGrath, A Fine-Tuned Universe, 186.
Great job, Tim. I hope you continue to find time to share your thoughts and research.
ReplyDelete